Thursday, May 30, 2024

On Van Lambalgen et al.'s formalization of Kant

The paper by Van Lambalgen and Pinosio 'The logic and topology of Kant's temporal continuum' (which is just one of a series of papers by Van Lambalgen on Kant)  opens with a nice discussion and careful justification of the general idea of the formalization of philosophical systems. The coined expression 'virtuous circle'  is particularly fortunate. In this post, which will be continuously updated, we will critically explore the above paper and make some connections with our own work on Aristotle's theory of the continuum.

The primitives are called 'events', self-affectations of the mind, which must be brought into order by fixed rules.  The authors work over finite sets of events which is justified by textual evidence from the CPR (we will return to this later).  Their task is to formalize relations between events - and to thus develop a point-free theory of the linear temporal continuum.

We find that that their notation could be improved and the axioms better justified. Instead of the confusingly asymmetric (all for the sake of the substitution principle, I suppose, or for the transitivity axiom) aRb and cR+d  let us write ab and dc. Instead of ab we write ab and insead of ab we write ab.

The basic idea is that : xy does not need to imply that xy or vice-versa.

Kant's concept of causality implies that in order for a part x of a to influence b we must have xb.  Thus the following axiom is expected

abb

But let us look at axiom 4 for event structures (in our notation):

cOb&ac&baaOb

Our task is to make sense of this by offering a more satisfactory account of the primitive relations. Let us consider the set of connected (hence simply connected) subsets of the real line R and the interpretations:

abxa.yb.xy

abxb.xa.xy

But this does not work for  abab. But let us take our events to be bounded open intervals (a,b) and consider

(a,b)(c,d)b<d

(a,b)(c,d)a<c

(a1,a2)O(b1,b2)a2>b1&a1<b2

Then if we consider (0,1) and (0,2) we have that (0,1)(0,2) but not (0,1)(0,2). The inequalities must be strict for allowing  (a,b)(a,b) is absurd, for then we could not associate any clear or definite Kantian philosophical concept with the relation.

Now let us look at axiom 4:

(c1,c2)O(b1,b2)&(a1,a2)(c1,c2)&(b1,b2)(a1,a2)(a1,a2)O(b1,b2) which becomes

c2>b1&c1<b2&a1<c1&b2<a2a2>b1&a1<b2

But this follows immediately, using in addition the fact that b2>b1. The condition c2>b1 appears not to be needed.

We could try defining (a1,a2)(b1,b2):=(a1,b2) when a1<b2 and (a1,a2)(b1,b2):=(b1,a2) when b1<a2.

This models should be introduced right at the start of the paper to motivate the the definition of event structure. Notice that the set of events is here identified with the (infinite) subset ER×R={(x,y):x<y} but we could take only a finite subset.

We must check the axioms for event-structures for our model and also give a geometrical interpretation of the relations and operations above in terms of the identification of E as a subset of the plane above.

No comments:

Post a Comment

We don't know what meaning is

Gödel, criticizing a paper by Turing, remarked on how 'concepts'  are grasped by the mind in different ways, that certain concepts c...